Kant
on mental illness, emotions and moral responsibility
Ilaria Ferrara·
Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici (I.I.S.F.),
Naples (Italy)
Abstract The paper discusses some
thematic issues that emerge from the Kantian study of diseases of cognition and
volition, taking into consideration his anthropological works and some problems
emerging from his main critical works. Starting from the explanation of the
taxonomy of the main mental illnesses (and their causes), some epistemological
themes will be illustrated, linked to the fallible relationship between
transcendental truths and the empirical dimension of knowledge and to the Kantian
concept of error. Subsequently, the study of affects and passions, conceived as
illnesses of volition, will show the difficulties linked to a total involvement
of reason in moral action, concerning the shortcomings of human action with
respect to the principle of responsibility. Finally, the paper will focus on
the role of legal imputability in
relation to moral responsibility and to mental diseases.
Key
words Kant; knowledge; moral; mental illness; legal
imputability; pathology
1. Kant, philosophy and medicine.
It is a relevant fact that Kant puts his study of
mental illnesses only in his pragmatic anthropology, rather than in his
Critical works and, consequently, does not focus on the theoretical
implications of mental pathologies for his transcendental system. In fact, in
his main critical works, Kant never refers to mental alterations, either in
relation to knowledge or in relation to practical reason. However, it was noted
that Kantian scheme of mental illnesses can be added to his transcendental work
to allow important features of his critical method to emerge regarding both
cognition and volition, because the diseases of the faculty of cognition and of
the faculty of feeling and desire potentially raise different questions in many
points of his philosophical project. The interpretation of a “corrective
dimension”[1]
of mental illnesses, if it has the merit of rehabilitating them within the
critical interest, loses the deeper meaning of mental pathology in Kantian
philosophy. In fact, it is difficult to identify Kantian psychopathology with
his “gnoseo-pathology”, i.e. to conceive his theory of mental pathologies based
totally on his theory of knowledge[2].
Mental illnesses, in fact, have a much more important role in Kantian moral
theory, as well as having an interesting development on questions relating to
the conception of the person and imputability. In this sense, I will try
to consider mental illness not only as a defect to be rectified but as a
relevant element for Kantian philosophy, from a theoretical and practical point
of view. The Kantian analysis of illness explains the errors, restrictions, and
obstacles in the formulation of judgments and, on the other hand, the emergence
of passions and affections interferes with the practical decision. It can be
said that, if mental illness has been investigated from a theoretical and
practical point of view in various studies, much less importance has been given
to its legal and moral interpretation.
In this paper, I will first introduce the relation
between medicine and philosophy in Kant’s work. I will focus first on the
epistemological and then on the moral aspects of mental illness. To conclude, I
will give an interpretation of the relation between imputability and mental
illness starting from the concept of personality. I will try to show that
mental illnesses have above all a relevant importance in Kantian moral philosophy.
Kant orders mental pathologies starting with the study
of the whole psychological faculty and its functioning – and problems -
(cognition, feeling, or desire). Kant – it is important to note - was not a
physician and his theory of mental ailments is not a real clinical theory. The
Kantian point of view is anthropological[3] but it provides advice on
the prevention and, partially, the cure of mental disorders. Kant also
criticizes the physiological approach to the study of mental illnesses
inaugurated in Platner’s anthropology,
in 1772, in the work Anthropologie
für Aerzte und Weltweise. According to Kant, in fact, this theoretical
model was not able to provide practical results relevant to the study of the
problem of the disease but was limited to a reductionistic and physical
investigation. However, Platner, professor and philosopher at Lipsia
university, was a follower of Leibniz and rationalist philosophy, and his
anthropology[4] was
important for some later philosophers and thinkers, such as Herder, Schiller
and Moritz. His anthropology, interpreted from a modern point of view,
considered human being in its unity and totality, through a psychosomatic
vision and a physiological and rationalist methodological approach. Platner
also placed psychosomatic medicine at the center of his reflection and his
concept of the unconscious [Unbewußtseyn],
coined in German for the first time, is relevant for subsequent theoretical
developments. The issue of mental illnesses is connected to the theme of the
relationship between body and mind in Kantian philosophy, a link that has only
recently been observed with attention. The theme of the body and disease is not
only connected to literary attention or to an acquired philosophical tradition
but also to a transcendental interest. In fact, although the body is a
traditional theme of the European Enlightenment, Kant links it to his
philosophy, both in the pre-critical phase, in relation to Leibniz and the
theories of predetermined harmony, and in the critical phase, to delimit what
is body and what is matter from what is not. In the following discussion I will
also try to develop the theme of the body in relation to disease and, above
all, the role of philosophy as a cure for the soul, beyond the function of
medicine conceived as a cure for the body.
The Kantian interest in mental illness arises in the
context of the birth of psychiatry, which is a discipline placed between
medicine and philosophy[5]
that collaborates with theology and jurisprudence. Starting from the intertwining
of these disciplines, Kant believes that the judgment on mental illness is
philosophical and it concerns the social responsibility of the sick subject. In
the relation between medicine and philosophy, Kant believes that the cause and
cure of physical diseases belong to medicine and to medical care. Illnesses of
the mind, on the other hand, are subjected to philosophical, anthropological
and psychological judgment. The Kantian approach to the disease of soul is formalistic, i.e. based on his theory of
knowledge and on a descriptive and non-physiological nosology. In this sense,
the Kantian model is very close to German tradition and diseases are not
explained through their causal relations, but only through their clinical
recognition. The Kantian reflection on mental illness is also an interesting
contribution of traditional debate on the “organ of the soul” and of the theory
of pathologies of the mind in Germany at the end of the eighteenth century. The
work of psychiatry, also called the “experimental science of the soul”, went
beyond “pragmatic physiology”, which was connected instead to a simply
classificatory work of empirical description. The interest in the new
psychiatric knowledge increased the study of the relation between bodily
functions and faculties of the mind. In addition, great attention was given to
the development of neurological and anatomo-cerebral investigation. In this
respect, most of the studies focused on the difficult relationship between
physical sensations, perceptions and consciousness flow and the disease of the
soul was interpreted as
originating in activity of the central
nervous system. In 1808, J. C. Riel
coined the term “psychiatry” (in German “psychiatrie”)
and introduced a distinction between the ganglionic and cerebral systems. From
this point of view, mental illness is explained by the distorted activity of a
single spiritual force and the soul is interpreted as an activity and not as a
unitary substance. From this, the investigation of the disease of the mind
becomes difficult since it is not possible to directly investigate the work of
the brain, which is considered the seat of the soul. Acting on mental illness
does not foresee acting directly on the brain but on the whole life of the
soul. Reil refers to the Kantian work The
Conflict of the Faculties[6]
(1798) and, in this sense, his treatment of pathologies also has a moral value.
There is, in fact, an “interest of reason” which considers the representations
of psychic life not simply in a theoretical sense but, above all, in a
practical meaning. Psychiatric treatment is also necessary for a moral purpose,
conceived as the realization of man’s unity in his spiritual conscience.
The relation between Kant and medicine is also
explained through his letters and correspondence. Kant had many relations with
famous physicians and, among all the scientists of that period, he certainly
had important intellectual exchanges with S. Th. Sömmering[7]
and D. C. Hufeland. In the letters of August 10 and September 17, 1795, Kant
replies to Sömmering's work on the Organ
of the soul (Über das Organ der Seele)[8].
The Kantian answer, both scientific and philosophical, was added by Sömmering
to his book, published the following year. According to Kant it is not possible
to speak of the physical seat of the soul but only of its organ, because the
soul does not have a specific material and space-time determination.
Interpreted as a mere virtual and dynamic presence, the soul cannot be
interpreted as the ventricle of the brain (sensorium
commune) in which the nerves intertwine. It is possible, in fact, to define
the place only of something material and not of a fluid contained in the brain
cavity. Kant admits that there is a separation between body and soul that
philosophy and medicine must accept. The concept of the position of the soul
for Kant is therefore contradictory because it requires a local presence and a
spatial quality of a thing that is an object of inner sense. To indicate the
brain as the physical seat of the soul means to give a judgment of subreption,
that is to confuse the traces of the impressions exerted on the brain with
thoughts, through laws of association.
Another important
reference is Hufeland, who, with his essay Die Kunst das menschliche Leben zu verlängern[9] (1797) allows Kant to reflect on a dietetic of Galenic
tradition. Following a modern configuration of a “psychosomatic” Kant responds
to Hufeland through the idea that the preservation of the body is also a moral
self-preservation[10], based on the
Stoic principle of the “substine et
abstine”. The prevention of diseases of the body is achieved through the
strength of the spirit and soul; philosophy, which is also understood as a
medical art, explains the power of the soul [Gemüt, also animus] over
sick bodily sensations and that ability to discriminate pathological sensations
from healthy ones. The relation between moral disposition and dietetic is interpreted by Kant as an
anthropological-pragmatic connection between acting and suffering, between the
ability to control negative impulses and the conservation of one's physical
health. In this sense, the answer to Hufeland is presented above all in the
third part of the Conflict of Faculties
and in Anthropology from a Pragmatic
Point of view (1798), through the concept of Gemüt, understood as the capacity of the soul to become autonomous,
in its representation, from its connection with affection. In fact, Kant
defines the Gemüt by referring
explicitly to the Stoic and Latin tradition of Cicero and Lucretius and to that
faculty capable of contrasting old age and illness. These references help to
understand the articulated relation between medicine and philosophy in Kantian
thought, within an interest between gnoseology, anthropology and morality. The
cure of mental illness is for Kant a moral goal, but also a specific
characteristic of humanity. But how is pathology of mind (conceived as brain
lesions or severe mental insufficiencies), understood as a deviation of reason
or absence of reason, justified? And, above all, how can the behavior of the
mentally ill be reconciled with the categorical imperative?
2. The Essay on
Maladies of Mind: mental illness, equilibrium of the faculties and society.
The taxonomy of mental illness is shown by Kant in two
works, in the Essay on Maladies of the
Head[11](1764) and in Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of view[12](1798).
Between the work of 1764 and Anthropology,
Kant develops the themes of madness during his academic lessons, without
following an analytical method. However, in 1964 Kant also wrote the Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful
and the Sublime[13], which has the
same object and the same phenomenological and descriptive method of the Essay: the method of observational
analysis of temperaments and their degenerations is similar to the description
of the alterations of mental illnesses. Another analogy between the two works
is that the diagnosis of the disease is based on the observation of human
behavior and, moreover, mental deviation is connected to the moral constitution
of the subject. In the Observations a
psychology of temperaments is presented and the only degenerate
"alteration" is related to the melancholy attitude. In the Observations there is no
psychopathological theory and the symptoms of mental illness, that is, hallucinations,
are manifested only in the melancholy. Pathological traits are explained as a
degeneration of the “normal” characteristics of the personality. Furthermore,
as in the essay of 1764, Kant notes the influence of the disease on
intersubjective relationships and the reactions of the social environment.
In the 1764 Essay,
Kant realizes a classification of “diseases of the head” (“krankheiten des kopfes” is used in literal translation, but to use
modern language we can say “diseases of the mind”, or “psychiatric diseases”).
Kant’s attention is focused on two points: on the one hand, the social and
ethical theme of Rousseau and the English moralists, and on the other, the
gnoseological theme of criticism of German rationalist metaphysics. According
to Locke’s distinction between mental weakness and madness, taken from Leibniz
and from German philosophy, the study of the deviant traits of a sick
personality is used by Kant to fix the possibilities and limits of reason in
its normal use. Generally speaking, Kant divides the deficiencies (weakness) of
the mind [Gemütsschwächen] from the
diseases of the mind [Gemütskrankheiten].
In both cases, Kant believes that the pathology disrupts the operational
functions of the faculties. This is an important aspect, especially for the
critique of traditional metaphysics and for the construction of a system of
principles and concepts based on precise transcendental structures. Mild
disorders are intellectual deficits or illnesses such as foolishness and
nonsense. These hit the Witz, the Verstand, the Urteilskraft, and the Vernunft.
Serious disorders, on the other hand, which concern perceptual and cognitive
alterations, affect the lower cognitive faculty, the Urteilskraft and the Vernunft,
understood as higher cognitive faculties. More specifically, the nosology of Essay is divided into two central
figures: either illness emerges because the imagination loses all contact with
sensibility and considers its ghosts and images as real, or because the
information of the senses is distorted by erroneous forms of judgment. In both
cases, that is, in hallucinations and ravings, a correct elaboration of reality
connected with sensibility is not given and the imagination, connecting
sensible data, doesn’t work. In the case of illness, in fact, instead of
figurative syntheses of the imagination, we have ghosts or illusions which are
separate projections from the data of reality. In these cases reality is
completely lost and the speech of the mentally ill person is expressed in the
vacuum of the separation between the psychic sphere and reality. According to
Kant, on the other hand, a good balance of the mind occurs when the data
offered by sensibility are processed so that the result corresponds to things
as they really happened. In the case of mental illness, however, there is no
connection between reality and the mind, so an ill person is in a non-real
dimension. Among the most serious perceptual and cognitive disorders, Kant
therefore includes alterations and fantasies (chimeras) and the various
disorders of judgment [Wahnsinn], of
reason [Wahnwitz] and of judgments of
experience [Aberwitz]. The faculty of
understanding [Verstand] assumes the
general role of a higher faculty distinct from judgment and reason. Judgment,
which has the function of comparing a predicate with a concept, can make a
logical error if it falsely associates empirical notes with a concept. In this
way, the defect of the insane is in the construction of a defective logical
connection, given by an erroneous syllogistic deduction.
The point of view of the Essay is close to the Dreams
of a Spirit-Seer (1766)[14],
where Kant, in his criticism of dogmatic metaphysics, adopted the empirical
tradition. The ideal of a right reason and a right knowledge is based on
empiricist gnoseology, according to which thinking real objects means referring
to data that derive from our sensations. In particular, regarding the
methodology, the procedure found in those years is based on an analytical
knowledge that is able to eliminate the sources of error and illusion through
the impartial analysis of phenomena, examined in detail and divided into their
ultimate elements. From Newton, Kant takes up the substitution of the principle
of synthetic explanation of essences towards an observational method of
phenomena in their empirical connections: the analysis of confused concepts of
experience takes place through the isolation, subdivision and comparison of the
notes of the given concept. Analysis, in this conception, is a philosophical
method that is based on the experience, allowing the decomposition of its
infinite aspects, and trying to find the principles that can organize the
manifold observed. The analytical method, however, also finds insoluble
concepts (from ethics, aesthetics, religion, feeling) to be such that they
cannot be fully explained through observation, because of the fallibility and
limitation of human capacities. Regarding mental illnesses, the visionary and
the mentally ill have common characteristics and are described in a similar way
through the same neurophysiological theory based on the principles of optics
and on the Cartesian doctrine of material ideas. For both, there is a
displacement of the object produced by the imagination, which from a simple
chimerical figure is projected as an external and “real” physical object. In
this case, the alteration connected to the judgments of experience is an
overcoming (the German prefix “aber”
means “passing forward”) of the limits of experience, in the same way as the
metaphysician or the visionary who does not remain within the limits imposed by
reason. Kant, therefore, associates the Essay’s
creative faculty of invention [schöpferische
Dichtungsfähigkeit] with the Dreams’ imagination
[Einbildungskraft], both are distinct
from the higher cognitive faculties and in close relation with the sensibility.
Finding the operative site affected by mental illness, Kant also establishes
the limit beyond which the use of the cognitive faculties is illegitimate.
Kant considers mental illness deriving from bodily
defects, according to the medicine of Boerhaave and Hoffmann, but mental
illness is also considered a disease of the soul. The soul, in this context, is
the center of man’s passions. Passions come true within the social environment
and, in particular, it is in society that pathological forms of the mind can
arise. The Essay on the Maladies of the
Head is important because Kant proposes a new cultural model, instead of
the deterministic model, which refers to medicine as a therapeutic science.
According to the cultural model - a paradigm that Kant will abandon in the
critical phase - Kant gives a description and an etiology of mental illness
starting from the relationship that the human being has with his social
environment. In society, Kant observes, there is attention to appearance and to
all those artificial rules that concern public behavior in social life. In this
context, as Kant observes, natural passions can be transformed in an unnatural
way of life and, for this purpose, society can become the origin of the
expression of mental illness. The problem of the Observations is that even if moral judgment is given by an
immediate feeling, in particular of the sublime, from a Kantian point of view a
moral philosophy that based its rules exclusively on that feeling is exposed to
a lack of universality and necessity. So, Kant integrates the moral conceptions
of the English moralists, based on the study of man in his peculiar nature,
with Rousseau’s ethics, in order to link a moral of sentiment with a rational
morality. Kant searches, through the study of Rousseau’s philosophy, for a new
method for the study of man, conceived as an absolute and ideal concept and
assuming it as a basis for psychological descriptive ethics, through the
phenomenal observation of behavior. The outlined human ideal is given by two
points of view, i.e. a state of natural and instinctive perfection and a state
of spiritual perfection, within which the history of humanity is conceived in
its efforts and errors. The morality is based on a philosophy of history, and
not only in an anthropological and individual sense. In this sense the social,
juridical and psychological elements that ground the moral rules are very
important for Kant, in a first step the principle of prudence, according to an
anthropological-pragmatic attention, and then an ethical-normative dimension.
Social dimension is a sphere of interest that is evaluated by Kant from a calm
observation of the illusory play of appearance to a decisive criticism of
costumes. In this context, in which the human is conceived by its specific
nature and in its ways of social living, Rousseau’s work is crucial, because it
is able to offer, beyond the Newtonian method of analysis, a new methodology,
which can orient and guide the investigation in the experience and existence.
Kant shows the passage from the degeneration of human nature to the unnatural
state of civilization[15].
The critique of society, that is explained by the criticism of excess of human
desire, is grounded on an immoderate enjoyment and a cult of the superfluous
and the opulence of customs. While Kant shows the degeneration of social life,
he believes that in this negative dimension of civilization there are the tools
to overcome decay. The Kantian observation, in fact, aims to unmask all the
levels of human behavior in society and, at the same time, tries to show the
origin of civilization, beyond its illusory artifice. The real decay of
civilization is characterized, according to Kant, by the stereotypical
formality of good taste, by the anesthetization of society that reduces virtue
to a mere semblance, compromising social life. The Kantian critique of the
barbarization of customs is also extended to politics, culture and religion. In
this perspective, Kant is close to Rousseau and to his concept of cultural and
educational revolution. Kant derives from Rousseau the research for an original
foundation of the concept of humanity, starting from a critique of current
customs and reaching an original state of nature, where the conditions and the
feelings of beauty and dignity are found. Kant analyzes the pathological
aspects of civilization, but he finds a revolution of customs, because he does
not believe that man can go back to a naive and primitive stage. The discourse
is articulated through the identification of a shared and universal dimension
of human nature, which is not comparable to transcendental subjectivity. Kant
shares with Rousseau the following conception: the ability of man in the state
of nature is based on a search for a feeling of freedom and independence from
the bonds of society, in an immediate feeling of justice and religiosity. On
the other hand, there are many differences between the two authors. First of
all, in Kant’s view, the state of nature is not characterized by an absolute
goodness of man, even if primitive man tends to be morally good and does not
need to cure his instincts because they are naturally oriented towards good.
However, unlike Rousseau, the Kantian savage does not have a universal feeling
of pity and sympathy. According to Kant, in fact, it is necessary to start not
from a natural a priori, in order to
be able to define the historical forms in which civilized man is determined,
but to proceed analytically and genealogically, it is important to stay on the
level of the civilized and modern man, identifying the possibility of social
reform, through the observation of the pathological problems that characterize
him. In fact, the Kantian analysis of the virtues of civilized man is divided into
positive and degenerate characters, that is, on the one hand, into temperaments
cultivated and supported by morality and, on the other hand, morals corrupted
by society. From this point of view, the same human character can degenerate or
be "cured" through a progressive social revolution which also affects
the imposition of a precise moral habit.
According to Kant, the exasperation of artificial life
and of behavior conceived as the set of rules and code of actions, becomes a
negative human model in contrast with natural spontaneity, which can cause
mental disturbs, because the man of society can risk madness[16]. This Kantian conception
is a reworking of Rousseau's thought, according to the idea of typical
anti-Enlightenment radicalism shown in the pre-critical period works. From this
perspective, the cause of madness is social living and, therefore, Kant is
interested in a dietetics of the mind. After the essay of 1764, Rousseau's
naturalism becomes a central concept of Kantian morality. In fact, in 1763 Kant
was a Newtonian scientist, a scholar of logic who was careful to separate the
structures of deductive thought from causal inferences. From the moral point of
view he distinguished a duty conditioned by an absolute obligation, and yet the
ethical and aesthetic sphere was dominated by English and Scottish
sentimentalists. In this atmosphere Kant reads the Emil or On Education of Rousseau and the Nouvelle Eloise. In the Observations,
Rousseau's philosophy is central in Kantian reflections. In this perspective,
madness is not conceived as a degrading return of man to bestiality, but as a
general effect connected with social conditions of life. According to Kant, in
nature, the three faculties of sensibility, imagination and understanding are
balanced and work in perfect accord with the natural environment. The
relationship between man and the environment is perfectly adequate and passions
are balanced in natural man in a total vision of energetic harmony (in this
sense, the English tradition of society joins the German vitalistic culture of
life). In these natural conditions, the mentally ill person is naturally ill,
that is, he has the misfortune of not having sufficient physiological
endowment. It is instead social life that breaks this balance, because it produces
strategies, fictions, artifices and attitudes. The artificial construction of
man in society has a potential imbalance, and diseases derive from the social
condition of life. Just like in Rousseau’s thought, it is the confusion of
natural passions that creates the conditions of illness, and the human
condition in society explains the possible alteration of the relation between
imagination and understanding.
3. The critical-epistemological relapses of mental
illness: a reflection on Anthropology from
a Pragmatic Point of view (1798).
The work of 1764 proposes a nomenclature of mental
illnesses [eine Onomastik der Gebrechen
des Kopfes], from paralysis, to foolishness, to madness, ranging from the
simplest grades of disease to the most serious mental illnesses. The Essay still appears immature as regards
a precise arrangement and classification of the faculties from a transcendental
point of view and, however, here Kant fixes mental illnesses in some figures
that will remain substantially the same even in the classification offered in Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of view.
Regarding Anthropology, Kant
distinguishes two specific disorders starting from the cognitive faculties, weaknesses
and illnesses. The first derive from a deficiency of cognitive power or
from a decreased function of that power. The latter maintain a partially
positive relation with the cognitive faculty but, although there is
correspondence, the operations of causal laws are different from the activity
of a subject in normal conditions. In particular, Kant conceives the taxonomy
of mental illnesses starting with cognitive powers in their legitimate and
transcendental use, to be able to study any anomalies, deficiencies and
defections. This is possible because Kant considers mental deficiencies and
mental illnesses as defects of the
cognitive faculty. Furthermore, Kant believes that the illnesses affect the
higher faculties and not the senses. In this sense, diseases are deviations of
the higher cognitive faculty [Verstand].
The defect of sensibility is not in the organ that receives the manifold but in
the faculty of the rules, i.e. it concerns the faculty of understanding and the
reason.
It is interesting to see how anthropology’s treatment
of mental illnesses is a theoretical “return” to the gnoseological themes
addressed in the Critique of Pure Reason (1787)[17].
Through the study of mental illnesses, Kant proposes the scheme of the
transcendental faculties from another point of view and thinks about the
possible errors of “pure reason”. First of all, the higher faculty of cognition
has many specific aspects. The faculty of understanding, through a priori
principles and concepts, brings to one’s representations the transcendental
unity experience: in this way, Kant builds a conception of the world conceived
as an objective synthesis of phenomena. Secondly, reason is a theoretical
ability to produce ideas, starting from the predicative activity of the faculty
of understanding and based on a specific logical faculty of syllogisms. Finally,
the power of judgment, based on the concept of aesthetic and teleological
reflection, has two kinds of deficiencies that derive either from an absence of
capacity (stupidity) or from a reduced function of this power. The ailments
listed by Kant follow from the alterations in the functioning of these
faculties. Insanity (Wahnwitz, insania) is a “deranged power of
judgment”: in this case, the ordinary function of judgment and its power to
make analogies is confused with the activity of understanding, and with its
power to relate the particular under concepts a priori, in a confusion
of faculties and of operations. In particular, insanity is a disturbance of the
content of thought in which the syllogistic structure is intact but the error
consists in false application of the rules. Judgment can, in fact, create false
analogies or fallacious syllogisms. The insane person mistakes a logical
presumption for a rational deduction, concludes the total identity of the
subjects from a partial identity of the predicates, and treats different
species as belonging to the same species. Amentia (Unsinnigkeit, amentia)
is a defect of imaginative association and regards the perversion of the
understanding as the inability to bring one’s representations into the
necessary coherence for the possibility of experience; craziness (Aberwitz;
vesania) is a “sickness of a deranged reason. - The mental patient flies
over the entire guidance of experience and chases after principles that can be
completely exempted from in touchstone, imagining that he conceives the
inconceivable.. The squaring of the circle… and the comprehension of the
mystery of Trinity are in his power.”[18] In this kind of disease
of unbalanced reason, the mentally ill person goes beyond the whole experience
and aims at incomprehensible principles. Deficiencies and derangement also
belong to the lower faculty of cognition, which includes the outer senses, the
inner sense (which is an activity of introspection of one’s own metal states)[19]
and the imagination. While the outer senses are not essential for the beginning
of illness, according to Kant the inner sense plays a fundamental role. In
fact, the inner sense does not have in itself the origin of illness or some
kind of deficiency but is subjected to illusions and “can easily lead to
enthusiasm and madness”[20] because there may be “a
confusion in the mind of supposed higher inspirations and powers flowing into
us”. From the imagination derive also the deficiencies of the reproductive
activity of imagination that Kant calls absent-mindedness, an involuntary
distraction of the representations. Dementia (Wahnsinn) is a mental
ailment of imagination through which “owing to the falsely inventive power of
imagination, self-made representations are regarded as perceptions”[21]. Kant also finds other
mental deficiencies, linked to the faculties. The deficiency of imagination is
distraction; a lack of wit is obtuseness; a lack of judgment is defined as
stupidity and, in the end, one with a weakness of understanding is called a
simpleton[22]. To
sum up, in the Unsinngkeit, the
madman remains in the experience; in Wahnsinn
and Wahnwitz the insane person acts
within the territory of experience but provides a wrong interpretation of it;
in the Aberwitz he crosses the
experiential boundary. It is important to observe how Kant qualifies diseases
and their severity starting from their level of overcoming the limits of
knowable experience. The mentally ill person, in Anthropology, is one who makes logical errors, falls into
prejudices, or does not adapt concepts to experience.
In Kant’s mind, as we said, mental ailments originate
from various circumstances. First of all, a mental illness can derive from a
“physical illness that requires medical attention”[23] or, it can sometimes be
based on a specific human predisposition, such as a hereditary cause or genetic
and familiar physiology. Mental deficiencies can also derive from a combination of environmental and
hereditary aspects but, in general, Kant is not worried about the defects of
the higher cognitive powers, because the critique of pure reason, with its
investigation into the limits and validity of correct reasoning, is also an
instrument which is capable of distinguishing healthy reasoning from “sick”
reasoning. Once the diagnosis of mind defects is clear, Kant reflects above all
on ways to cultivate cognitive powers, through an anthropological and pragmatic
point of view. In fact, Kant theorizes a natural therapeutic modality, to
prevent or definitively eliminate the disturbs. The pragmatic point of view, in
fact, is based on the idea that an individual can live with various mental
disorders and, in this sense, the role of the soul physicist is not exclusively
that of curing the sicknesses of the mind but also that of helping the
individual to live with it. In fact, some mental pathologies are incurable
because they have a biological basis, but they are simply observable and
classifiable, that is, it is possible to live with them and, at the same time,
compose a reasoned taxonomy. However, as we have seen, Kant suggests a
non-biological cause of diseases of the mind, in the “most profound degradation
of humanity” where “the only universal characteristic of madness is the loss of
common sense and its replacement with logical private sense”[24].
In some figures of mental illness, in fact, there is a kind of nihilistic
delirium[25],
in which the unity of consciousness is broken. The incorrect application of the
categories by the mentally ill person excludes him from the unity of “I think”
and from the legislation of nature. In mental illness, according to Kant, there
is a private sense of logic in
relation to objects. The theoretical-transcendental principles of the mentally
ill, in this sense, cannot say anything about the unity of experience.
Furthermore, the mentally ill person has a formal inability to unify the
experience because he makes mistakes in applying this capacity. The limits of
the mentally ill are related to the application of concepts and are connected
to the use of rules and language. In the case of a hereditary disease,
according to Kant, the patient cannot control his impulses or correct his
logical inability and illness does not derive from a “bad” or “wrong” use of
reason. Kant distinguishes several pathologies: on the one hand, there are serious
diseases that require psychiatric assistance; on the other, Kant admits that
pragmatic anthropology can help the patient to correct his “mistakes”. In the
latter case, in fact, Kant speaks of a
“diminution” and not of a “cancellation” of humanity. The mentally ill patient
is still “human” but will have an epistemic and moral humanity of a
“particular” kind.
Kantian treatment of mental illnesses has also
important gnoseological and epistemological implications because is able to
show the limitations, dangers and difficulties that transcendental philosophy
hides. As noted by P. Frierson (2009), mental illnesses bring significant
problems to the assumptions of criticism and raise questions that lead to a
renewed analysis of the principles of the Critique of Pure Reason.
Kantian philosophy, as it is explained in the first Critique, does not study
the possible errors deriving from an incorrect application of transcendental
principles (which is a topic studied above all in logical writings and
lectures), but it focuses on the construction of experience through the
ordering of the manifold offered by space and time and by the unification of
the understanding which confers universality and necessity. The Critique of Pure Reason does not
investigate the mistakes given by the application of its principles but it
studies how its rules process phenomena in a valid and correct way, through the
discovery of a transcendental logic. Critique is, first of all, an
investigation into limits and possibilities, not about objects but about a
priori concepts of objects in general. Critique opposes the failure of
dogmatism which has generated skepticism and the illusion of metaphysical
knowledge, which are followed as a reaction to dogmatism. With the critique of
pure reason, then, Kant offers a cure
to skepticism, since it aims to discover if pure a priori knowledge is possible
and what its extension is. From the critical investigation it appears that
reason is the faculty from which the fundamental concepts and the a priori principles
arise and from which all other a priori knowledge can be deduced. The critique
is a propaedeutics to the system of
pure reason, that is, a science that judges pure reason and the sources of this
knowledge, by determining its limits. The critique investigates whether this a
priori knowledge can be applied in an unlimited way to supersensitive objects
or only to sensitive objects. For this reason, the critique is not the doctrine of
pure reason but the critique of it, that is, its object of study is not
knowledge, but the field from which knowledge arises. The aim of the critique
of pure reason extends to all the claims of the cognitive faculty in order to
see its validity. The task of critique of pure reason is negative and its
function is restrictive. In this sense, the critique is a “cure” of
transcendental knowledge.
As we have seen, the study of mental illnesses is
necessary to consider a general problem of knowledge, since it reveals negative
aspects of reasoning in its operations. In a discussion on the possibility of a
priori knowledge, the role of contingent elements relating to human nature
is highly relevant, within the constitution of a unitary and objective
cognitive experience. In this regard, the logical dimension, which is expressed
in an adequate application of the a priori principles of understanding, could
also be determined by some psychological elements and, thus not necessarily
guarantee objective knowledge. For example, these psychological limitations
could be derived from genetic, hereditary defects, from mental malformations.
These “physiological” defects could certainly have an impact on the logical
level of knowledge processing. The conditions of a transcendental philosophy is
connected to the fact that the truths at the basis of exact science[26]
(mathematics and logic), from a Kantian point of view, are based on the
subjective principle of our way of feeling (through space and time) and
unifying (through the categories) a complete experience of the world[27].
Starting from this conception, the logical, mathematical and geometric truths
must be true in every world built, according to our transcendental principles.
Kant does not study this distinction between truth of facts and truth of
reason, but the transcendental deduction of the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason is in opposition
to a particular psychologism of his
conception of the faculties. The deduction of the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason has a more
realistic structure, since Kant rejects the psychological and subjective
organization of the faculties taken up by J.N. Tetens (Tetens speaks about
three faculties and three syntheses of a subjective deduction), according to
which there is a generating function of the objective world. The
anti-psychologistic and anti-subjectivist perspective of the second
transcendental deduction can be understood starting from the subtraction of
time from the synthesis of the manifold and its consequent generalization. This
passage between the first and second transcendental deduction marks a turning
point in Kant's conception of transcendental knowledge. The imagination
acquires a subordinate function to the categories in the process of knowledge
and, with the abolition of time from the synthesis of the manifold, a generalization
of the function of categories takes place, not only connected to the
organization of the sensible but now considered within a transcendental logic.
In this sense, Kant divides, on the gnoseological level, the laws of empirical
and psychological association, still present in the subjective deduction, from
the transcendental function of categories.
To summarize, the possibility of the relation between
a valid and true knowledge, which is also objective and based on logical and
formal laws, and the presence of these transcendental principles in a finite
subject which is subjected to psychological and physical limitations, is a
complex point of Kantian philosophy. In this way, Kantian transcendental
philosophy is based on a discovery of theoretical and moral principles that are
able to guarantee truth and validity to knowledge of the world and of action.
Euclidean space as an order of coexistence, and time conceived as an order of
succession, are based on pure principles of universal and necessary sensibility,
which are valid for everybody. In the same way, the intellectual categories
with which we build phenomena and objects of experience are the same in
everyone and are conceived as the principles of reunification of the manifold
of a shared experience from an intersubjective point of view. The problem will
then concern the validity of such truths, based always and in any case on human
nature and, for this reason, the problem is based on the difficulty of defining
them as necessary or as endowed with logical evidence. In this sense,
transcendental rules govern healthy reason and the normal operations of the
higher cognitive faculty. Nevertheless the human being can err through various
restrictions and subjective obstacles, not proceeding within his own normative
standards, because it is possible to make mistakes by formulating judgments
inappropriately. In this sense, a healthy intellect can make mistakes; the sick
intellect does not simply make mistakes, but radicalizes them into a coherent
and “new” model of reality.
Kant believes that the healthy faculty of
understanding is the same faculty capable of elaborating coherent judgments in
a good relationship between sensibility and understanding, in which there are
no irregular interferences. This is a sign of Kantian principle of harmony of the faculty that Kant
maintains in the first and, above all, the Critique
of Judgment (1790)[28]
and in which the correct operations of the cognitive faculties is supported
through the discovery of a new a priori principle. The healthy reason presents
an objective unity of the relation between the imagination and the
understanding. This means that the imagination operates a first organization of
the empirical manifold by figurative syntheses, which are subjected to the synthesis
of categories. According to Kant there is also a subjective unity of the
relationship between imagination and intellect, that is, the free play of faculties that occurs in
aesthetic judgment[29].
Furthermore, in the latter case the faculties are connected to each other
according to a principle of finality and harmony and they determine specific
aesthetic and non-cognitive judgments. In both cases, the functioning of the
faculties does not close the individual into selfishness deprived of a solitary
knowledge, since the correctness of the judgments is based on the sanity of the
intellect, guaranteed by the order and unity of the representations in
transcendental apperception.
If in his critical works Kant focuses on the harmony
between the faculties in their functioning, in his lessons[30]
he uses the term prejudice [Vorurtheil] to indicate the way in which
reason can make mistakes, interfering in the regular connections of judgments[31].
In the conception of the limits and validity of human knowledge, in fact, it is
necessary to consider that there may be other forms of reasoning which are
capable of overcoming the boundaries of human knowledge as understood from an
objective point of view and, in this sense, Kant reflects on the possibility
that human beings have different cognitive structures. The treatment of
pathologies does not establish their absolute negativity, since Kant discusses
the conditions, the causes and the possible prevention of the illnesses,
without considering what, on the other hand, would be healthy situations. In
cases of craziness or insanity Kant then manages to find an unnecessary level
of contingency for human nature, which proceeds beyond the coherence of
transcendental truths “In this… kind of mental derangement there is not merely
disorder and deviation from the rule of the use of reason but also positive
unreason; that is, another rule, a totally different standpoint into which the
soul is transferred, so to speak, and from which it sees all objects
differently.”[32] A
mentally ill person is described as one who lives in a different world, and in
which “the powers of the unhinged mind still arrange themselves in a system”
and “even arrange cognitions according to “a principle of unity”[33]. He who is mentally
disturbed, according to Kant, lives with “a totally different standpoint” and
even if the “objects must conform to our cognition” Kant declares that the
afflicted person lives “in his own world”[34]. If Frierson’s reading of
logical variations assumes a fundamental aspect of the relation between the
transcendental dimension and empirical psychology in Kant’s theory of
knowledge, his interpretation does not clarify the question of prejudices and
provisional judgments in Kantian logic. In some logic lectures, Kant clarifies
the difference between provisional
judgments and prejudices.
Prejudice is the “foundation” we have for judging something in advance [vorher], which however does not derive
from the laws of the understanding. It is a sort of “deviation” of the judging
from the application of the transcendental principles. Prejudices are described
as preliminary judgments that are misunderstood in their function. Provisional
judgments derive from objective foundations, prejudices from subjective
foundations; the former derive from reason, the latter from the sensibility
that distorts them. In this sense, provisional judgments seem to be exact
precognitions (which may come from experience), while prejudices are false
judgments, formulated without a sufficient foundation, that is, without a ratio determinans. Kant insists on the
formal falsity of prejudices which remains fundamental even when these are
correct with respect to the content (i.e. "true"). A prejudice
remains a prejudice even when what it claims is true. If prejudices can be true
with respect to the content, they remain false as to the foundations (i.e. the
way they were obtained and produced) and are therefore dangerous. The
consideration of the formal point of view concerns the degree of the affirmed
correctness of a judgment. Thus any persuasion is false with respect to the
form (formaliter) since here an
uncertain knowledge seems to be certain. The formal consideration of truth
consists in comparing the certainty required by a knowledge with the
foundations that exist to affirm that knowledge. If there is a contradiction
between the two aspects, then the knowledge is formally false, even if it may
be true regarding the content. The provisional judgment precedes the complete
or decisive judgment, and makes use of preliminary indications obtained from an
in-depth evaluation of an object. When this presumption is confused with a
definitive judgment, one falls into error. The act of formulating a judgment in
advance, based not on the laws of the understanding but on interference of the
sensibility with the intellect, is the logical prejudice. This, like mental
illness, generates erroneous beliefs and dangerous forms and constitutes a
crime even when good can be derived from it. Kant believes there are prejudices
that derive from habit and others that derive from authority. Prejudices,
therefore, from a logical point of view can have a content of truth but
formally be erroneous.
The errors that Kant lists from the various
pathologies are not, however, connected only to logical prejudices but to
problems of general application of principles and concepts in the formation of
judgments. Kant also refers to an incorrect comparison of predicates with
objects, to syllogistic defects, to errors given by illusory projections, to
the exchange of a logical presumption for a rational deduction. For this
reason, considering the error of the mental patient only as a variation or a
logical prejudice is limiting. In fact, this conception of logical errors,
arising from habit or authority, has an ancient tradition and, on this aspect,
Kant retrieves the theory of error from Galen’s medical school. In his treatise
on the cure of the passions, in fact, Galen does not deal with the healing of
diseases (and therefore with therapy) but with the cure of errors and passions.
Mistakes arise from a false opinion and concern a rational level; passions
arise from an irrational faculty. Similarly, as noted, pathology in Kant arises
from an imbalance of faculties and an error of reasoning. The cure of the
disease is a therapy of the error and the elimination of the elements that
favor its development. But Kantian mental illness is not simply produced by a
logical variation. This interpretation seems to conceive Kant’s work in a too
modern way. The idea that error is inherent in language and is given by
deceptions in conceptual and expressive relations is, above all, a conception
of contemporary logic (in Frege’s philosophy, for example). The error in Kant,
in addition to having a logical and linguistic function, is also an element
that concerns the more general limit of the use of transcendental principles.
However, a Kantian theory of error is useful for understanding one of the ways
in which mental illness is expressed, which has, above all, consequences on the
moral and anthropological level. The cure of the disease, understood as the
correction of the error, is only a limited part of the Kantian theory of mental
pathologies. In Kant’s theory, in fact, there is a moral conception of the cure
of illness, in which the rectification of a logical irregularity is only the
starting point of a deeper intervention.
To conclude, Kant believes that health is grounded on
the order of thoughts and representations, an order shared by all men. It is on
this basis that Kant can indicate the simple deficiencies and diseases of the
soul with respect to the faculty of cognition. Kant also believes that the
exercise of some small, controlled, and deliberated madness, especially reduced
to the private sphere of entertainment, such as hobbies, can be positive since
it keeps “vital forces always awake”. The diseases of the soul can be cured if
the soul collaborates to the order of the thoughts; when the disorder is
complete and the subject completely ignores the objective laws of
representations, there is no possible cure. There is a full and complete
interaction between the physical, animal, nature of man and his moral
rationality. Given this interaction, the senses and the understanding must
necessarily collaborate, since the disease can only be “felt” but the causes
must be investigated by the reason. Since health is the balance in the
antagonism of the vital forces of the animal body, and excitability (incitabilitas) in the nervous system and
irritability (irritabilitas) in the
muscular system are the driving forces, from which life is derived, then it is
reasonable to suppose that medicine is similar for men and for animals. The
difference is that for man the “preservation of himself in his animal nature”
is not just an instinct but a duty.
This conception of medical treatment, in which the
moral intention is closely connected to the therapeutic one, considers the
Kantian theory of pathology as a “philosophical” theory. This philosophical
theory is a “medicine of the soul”. According to Kant, therefore, while the
disorder based on a physical level must be treated by a doctor, the philosopher
can play a role, intervening in the parallel treatment of the soul. Because all
the ailments of the soul reveal an absence of order, philosophy is a form of treatment
of diseases. The order that all men can share, outside the solitary dreams of a
spirit-seer, is in fact the set of principles of transcendental philosophy
(that is, it is the order of universal and necessary laws that found and
regulate knowledge). Therefore, philosophy does not only offer the support for
establishing an objective order. Philosophy can also prescribe maxims for a
good use of the mind and against some disturbances of the mind – with positive
consequences for the body. It is up to the philosopher to ensure that the soul
does not become a cause of illness and suffering for the body, and above all to
evaluate the origin of some illnesses in the disturbance of the soul, and to
intervene on them as a guide, so that they are eliminated.
4. Defect of volition and of the principle of desire.
Besides the defects of cognition, related to the
faculty of understanding, Kant establishes a classification of the defects of volition,
starting from the faculty of desire and its operations. Indeed, just as
logical prejudices and disorders of the cognitive faculty compromise the right
production of objective knowledge, so too the higher faculty of desire (and the
faculty of feeling) may not function properly. Desire (appetitio) is “the self-determination of a subject’s power through
the representation of something in the future as an effect of this
representation. Habitual sensible desire is called inclination”[35].
The inclination, if it cannot be governed by the reason of the subject, is
defined as passion. The feeling of pleasure or displeasure which does not make
use of subjective reflection is emotion (affection).
While the correct functioning of the cognitive faculty is achieved by the
correct application of logical-transcendental principles through the
organization of the manifold through space and time and its unification in the
phenomenon through categories, the operation of the faculty of desire is
articulated in a different way. The faculty of desire, in fact, is divided into
two levels, the higher faculty of desire and the lower faculty of desire, and
in both cases the action is defined through the imposition of maxims. The
higher faculty of desire bases moral action on a pure law of reason. The lower
faculty of desire produces maxims which are material principles, that is, based
on an object of desire. Reason, conceived as a “whole” faculty, has a
theoretical use and a practical use. In this latter sense, pure reason is able
to determine the will by a principle, the moral law. This practical reason is
active every time there is an action based on a principle or on a calculation.
Every time we act, in a proper sense and not by instinct (and, for this reason,
Kant believes that the problem of the instinct must be studied in the context
of a possible empirical psychology
and not in a transcendental philosophy), we base our action on a maxim or
principle that is not necessarily rational. Acting through a principle does not
mean that the motivation for the action comes from pure reason and from the moral
law. In fact, it is also possible to determine the actions to obtain a certain
object of desire and the principle of the actions, in this case, is the simple
motivation for an object of desire. In this sense, the Critique of Practical Reason[36] (1788)
does not study deviations or errors of the faculty of desire. The analytics of practical reason analyzes
the practical principles of the will, of the objects and the motives, with the
aim of defining these elements according to the requirements of pure practical reason.
Even the study of the matter of desire, that is, of all the objects that give
pleasure and displeasure, is not a treatment about a “deviation” of the desire
faculty, according to Kant. The study of the material principles of the will
has its own specific dignity and completes the Kantian treatment of the faculty
of desire. In Anthropology, according
to Kant, the man who is subject to emotions and passions has an “illness of the
mind, because both affect and passion shut out the sovereignty of reason. Both
are also equally vehement in degree; but as concerns their quality they are
essentially different from each other”[37].
In this general perspective, the human capacity to
produce an action starting from principles of self-governance is subjected to
different forms of deviations, both from what is properly defined “evil” and
from two forms of defects of the volition, affects and passions. These defects
of volition compromise self-governance above all, questioning the human
principle of moral responsibility. In Metaphysics
of Morals (1797) and in Anthropology
of a Pragmatic point of View, Kant defines affects [Affekten] as a
“lack of virtue” and passions [Leidenschaften] as “properly evil”,
starting with his distinction between the lower faculty of desire and the
higher faculty of desire. In the general scheme concerning the description of
human motivation, the faculty of lower desire is motivated by the matter of
desire and feeling, desire and action follow from sensations not be mediated by
any principle of reflection on them. The higher faculty of desire, on the other
hand, has as a principle of reason as its reason for acting. According to Kant,
affects are “alterations” of the faculty of feeling and passions are “disturbs”
related to the faculty of desire. Affects and passions are defined as “illness[es]
of the mind": “agitations of soul are twofold, affects and passions…
Affect is a feeling through which we come out of composure [of soul]. Passion
is rather a desire that brings us out of composure”[38]. Affects and passions are
similar with regard to the loss of self-control and, more specifically, they
exclude the total government of reason in practical action. While differing in
faculties (or feelings or desires), affects and passions are not ordinary emotions
or feelings, such as, for example, inclinations. Even with regard to very
strong inclinations or feelings, Kant never refers to these elements
negatively, as sensations apt to corrupt moral action[39]. In Kant’s view, affects
are “not the intensity of a certain feeling that constitutes the affected
state, but the lack of reflection”[40]. Affects, according to
Kant, are “thoughtless” and suspend the mind’s composure, making reflection
impossible. In this contest, reflection is considered as “the representation by
means of reason as to whether he should give himself up to [the feeling] or
refuse it.”[41]
Affects arrive suddenly and flow away fastly, and Kant compares them to the physiological
states of the body, both referring to those that increase vital forces and to
those that relax the same forces. Kant speaks about affects starting from the
faculty of feeling and, for this reason, the discussion on these defects of
volition does not seem to concern their motivational efficacy. But the question
is more difficult than it seems. Kant links affections with physiological and
biological components that can compromise physical health above all. However,
in many places, Kant insists on linking the presence of an altered affect to
the motivation to act, because affects are bad and undermine agency. Since most
feelings are practical and fundamental to the cultivation of the practical
sphere, Kant focuses attention on the alterations of feelings and desires that
can compromise action, through the analogy with “temperaments of feeling”. The
study of temperaments allows Kant to grasp the connection between disordered
feelings and disordered actions. Temperaments are normally motivational and an
individual’s character is capable of determining action, through the faculty of
feeling. If there is an affection, a disorder, caused by a stronger feeling,
there is a "suspension of composure". In this case, affects do not
allow reflection and suspend the practical decision of a subject, conditioning
the higher faculty to desire. Affects are so overwhelming in the mind that they
overcome reflection and become principles of immediate causation of action,
disregarding the primacy of the faculty of cognition and of desire. In this
conception it is the body that becomes central and Kant associates this kind of
action, which favors only the lower faculty of feeling, to pure animal
instinctive action. In the Observations and in the Remarks, Kant
theorizes a positive circularity between aesthetic and moral factors within the
single principle of the Gefühl. Temperaments and human inclinations,
then, if adequately cultivated, provide the starting point for the formation of
a precise ethical habit. If, in fact, the ambit of temperaments and the virtues
connected to them can prepare one for the formation of an ethical attitude,
without there being the voluntary adequacy to a norm of reason, the altered
affects do not allow the healthy control of behavior towards oneself and
others. During the pre-Critical period, Kant had not yet organized the higher
faculties as the only proper locus of moral motivation, so a rational affect
could be explained as a legitimately moral source of moral motivation.
Like affects, passions are defined as illnesses of
mind that “shut out the sovereignty of reason”[42]. Passion is an
“inclination that prevents reason from comparing it with the sum of all
inclinations in respect to certain choice”.[43] Moreover, passions,
unlike affects, imply that “the calm with which one gives oneself up to [a
passion] permits reflection and allows the mind to form principles”[44]. In this sense, passions
involve reflection and they are conceived as “inclinations”. In moral
philosophy Kant uses the term “inclination” to define a ground of the lower
faculty of desire, where the sensations are strictly connected to the ambit of
volition. Inclinations, in Kantian philosophy, are not connected to instincts
and are not only related to the lower faculty of feeling or desire. Kant also
uses the term inclination to explain the reference of practical principles that
indirectly determine the higher faculty of desire and pursue ends imposed by
inclinations. In this sense, inclination is a principle that determines a
sensible end, in contrast with the purity of moral law and its principle. Kant
also thinks that passions are disordered inclinations that do not evolve
towards higher faculties. Nevertheless, identifying passions with inclinations
could imply that passions, as well as affections, exceed the superior faculty
of desire and could become motivating for action without relying on the
activity of deliberation and reflection. In Anthropology Kant writes “One can list being
passionately in love [among the passions] (as long the other party persists in
refusal), but one cannot list any physical love as passion, because it does not
contain a constant principle with respect to its object. Passion always
presupposes a maxim on the part of the subject, to act according to an end
prescribed to him by his inclination. Passion is therefore always connected
with his reason, and one can no more attribute passion to mere animals than to
pure rational beings.”[45] Therefore it seems clear
that passions allow reflection because they are particular inclinations,
understood as direct principles to inclinational ends. Again, in a handwritten
note: “Passion[s]… presuppose a sensible but nevertheless also a counteracting
rational faculty of desire (they are therefore not applicable to mere animals),
except that inclination in [animals] takes away pure practical reason, in
[passionate persons] dominat[es practical reason], taking possession of maxims
either in respect to one’s ends or the use of means toward them.” Passions,
then, do not exclude the role of imposing a maxim as a motivational principle
of action. However, in the case of passions, with respect to the giving of the
principle of pure moral law, the object will be offered by inclination and by
the matter of desire. For example, cold passions too (manias for honor,
dominance and possessions, for example) are not only connected with an
affection, but also with a maxim, determined by another kind of end, which is
not strictly moral. In the case of the passion for vengeance, Kant says that it
is motivated by a principle which is able to formulate maxims, a decision of
action but connected to desire. The passionate person is completely overwhelmed
by the principles imposed by his passion and his feeling and does not consider
the moral implications of his actions. Passionate action always requires a
particular intervention of the higher faculty of desire, even if the principle
governing action is passionate and reflection precludes both morality and
happiness. In fact, the truly passionate individual in love, does not consider
happiness or morality to be fundamental for his action, but only seeks out
maxims that can satisfy his own passion. He will have his own passion as the
end of this act, without any regard for any other kind of purpose.
The Kantian treatment of passions and affections holds
that the human being can act against his own interests and higher ethical
principles. Affections are disordered feelings that overcome the highest
faculty of feeling; passions are deep and persistent alterations of the higher
faculty but establish a different purpose from the moral one. According to
Kant, various forms of defects of will exist because human action is partially
connected to causes that can be explained from an empirical point of view. The
importance of human action is given by the fact that it is always an expression
of transcendental freedom and only because one possesses an intelligible level
of freedom is it also possible to explain the choice for actions or choices
ascribable to an empirical level. In the critical treatment Kant subordinates
to the practical law all the maxims and resolutions deriving from heteronomous
principles, giving a consistent priority to moral principles. The connection
between the defects of the will and mental illnesses is thus explained.
Cognitive pathologies that emerge from logical mistakes lead to a cognitive
solipsism. In the same way, there is something similar in the diseases that
emerge from the defects of volition. Affections and passions are extreme forms
of moral selfishness that Kant defines in Anthropology as the tendency
to seek ends not for duty but for happiness. The egoism to which they lead is
connected to the exclusive personal purpose of the passionate inclination,
excluding any reference to others or one’s own moral autonomy. But the mentally
ill and the wicked (or the criminal) are profoundly different, because the
former is not responsible for his actions, while the latter is capable of
thinking a subjective maxim.
In the previous section, we observed how the mentally
ill is unable to build a systematic unity of nature. Similarly, the Kantian
conception of the deviations and errors of the rules of reason has an ethical
implication. In this way, mental illness produces a form of alienation, i.e. an
inability to control impulses. When the cause of the disease is hereditary, the
responsibility for immoral behavior does not fall on a man conceived as a free
agent, but on his physiological structure. In these severe cases of mental
illness, an anthropological-pragmatic perspective of the cure is not useful.
The person compromised by a serious illness is not responsible for his “bad”
use of reason. In these cases, the patient is unable to correct his condition.
But, what “kind” of humanity does the mentally ill have? The decrease in the level of humanity of the
mentally ill is very difficult to understand. Kant believes that the mentally
ill is not a subject of free action but is only able to live and create his
personal world. A subject incapable of free action cannot be considered totally a person by Kant: the mentally
ill person is, in fact, guided by others, and he is not autonomous. In this
sense, then, the concept of “minority”, overcome by the Enlightenment, explains the state of the mentally ill, i.e. who is
unable to formulate ends and to use his reason without the guidance from another.
5. Mental illness and imputability: a possible
interpretation.
The study of the diseases of cognition and volition
explains the deficiencies and the distortions of human action as unusual errors
and problematic mistakes of the will, because not all free subjects are able to
adapt their action according to rational principles and the moral law. It is
important for Kant to analyze the non-moral motivations, because the laws of
empirical psychology, which can be considered as a discipline that treats the
principle of action not connected to the moral law, study motivation based on
desire, and not only on the spontaneity of law of freedom. If the Critique of Practical Reason, in the
part relating to the material determination of the principles of will, studies
the problem of desire and the material objects of pleasure, a discipline such
as empirical psychology is not developed by Kant as a systematic part of his
transcendental philosophy. In this sense, the study of the passions, of the
affections of the soul, as well as of the desirable aspects of action, fall
into anthropological works, although, as we shall see, they have a tangent
interest with some themes concerning the legal sphere.
The affections and passions of the soul are not
exclusively perturbations of the soul, but they are important elements through
which it is possible to understand that action is also subjected to a material
determination of the will[46],
to objects of desire, by a form of natural causality. Kant, in fact, says:
“affect does a momentary damage to freedom and dominion over oneself. Passion
abandons them and finds its pleasure and satisfaction in a slavish mind. But
because reason still does not ease off with his summons to inner freedom, the
unhappy man groans in his chains, which he nevertheless cannot break away from
because they have already grown together with his limbs, so to speak”[47]
. This quote is important for the connection between human passion, reason and
freedom. In the passion of the soul, man is constantly called to his internal
freedom, through practical reason. The passionate man, therefore, consciously
chains himself, “deciding” on passion as the principle of his action and not
for the moral law. The passionate man is aware of making a choice which is
capable of subverting the rational order of action.
In this regard, a problem of considerable importance
is the relation between mental illness and the imputability [Zurechenbarkeit] in
a moral perspective. In particular, as we will see, Kant focuses on the relation
between imputability and diseases of the mind, from a cognitive point of view
and from the point of view of the faculty of desire. In particular, the problem
is to understand the role of the subject’s health and his or her responsibility
in action and to establish the degree of guilt and the punishment that can be
given. According to Kant, the concept of legal imputation is based on the
possession of the complete functioning of the higher cognitive faculties. In
ethical writings, Kant links these higher faculties to action, through the
principle of freedom “we can attribute something to someone but not impute it
to him; the actions, for example, of a madman or a drunkard can be attributed
even if not imputed to them. In the indictment the action must spring from
freedom.”[48]
Therefore, when an action is due to diseases of the cognitive faculty, one can
be exempted from legal responsibility. Kant reduces the role of mental
disturbs, especially cognitive, in the dimension of juridical imputability but
highlights, in his Metaphysics of Morals[49] (1797), important implications of the
difference between affects and passions for moral responsibility. Kant
believes, in fact, that although affects and passions both hinder morality and
both interfere with the normal processes of rational choice. In this sense,
according to Kant, affects simply indicate a “lack of virtue”, while passions
are “really evil”. The affects, which exclude the reflection in the faculty of
feeling and interfere with choice, represent only a weakness. Weakness of mind[50],
as a loss of will in the principle of action, is not negative in itself and
concerns the inability to put a principle of reflection on motivation. For
example, a person may kill someone out of anger, but the power of choice, in
this case, is not involved. A person may not be able to provide assistance to
someone in need, but only because he is not capable of formulating relevant
wishes or desires. Acting or not acting because of affects is morally similar
to acting or not acting when one is asleep, or like suffering from
sleepwalking. In this case, one is morally unconscious and is not morally
corrupt, as the maxim of action is not a passionate principle but simply an
action followed by a loss of voluntary forces. For this reason, the affects do
not make the subject less virtuous, but he does not progress in virtue, because
the weakness of the will is neither doing evil nor progressing towards good.
Unlike affects, passions work through the power of choice of ends, choosing to
pursue the object of an inclination without reflections on other possible
objects of choice. Therefore passions are not simply weak states of mind, like
the affections, but they are also evil. Passions do not preclude the choice,
but intentionally pervert it and this is the principle of a radical evil. One
with passion deliberately rejects all interests, including moral law, in favor
of seeking an inclination. Therefore all passions are completely incompatible
with having good will.
The relation between legal imputability and mental
illness is not studied by Kant in an interrelated way. In Anthropology, therefore, Kant does not treat with the problem of
legal imputation directly[51],
but focuses on some problems concerning the relation between affections,
passions and moral responsibility. In particular, responsibility and freedom
appear strongly undermined starting from the passions of the soul - the real
diseases of the will - that Kant believes to be “cancers” of the soul: “passion
is cancerous sores for pure practical reason”[52].
Kant is clear in the definition of passion. Since the passion is expressed in
reflection, and is not a rushed movement like the affection (which is
temporary), it tends to take root and to be tied to “reasoning”. For this
reason, Kant sees passion as capable of becoming the object of a maxim of the
faculty of desire, in the same way as moral law. Passion offers a principle to
action, a motivation that is structurally linked to the basis of action.
Affection is a shattering excitement which disappears as soon as it is over.
Passions, says Kant, are not, like affects, “unfortunate states of mind” but
are “evil as well”[53].
Kant connects passion to reason, studying the difference between man and
animal. The impetuous inclination of the animal, expressed in the animal
instinct (the inclination for sexual union) and in the research for means of
subsistence, is not passion, because the animal is not reasonable. For this
reason, as Kant says “animals […] have no reason, which alone establishes the
concept of freedom and with which the passion comes into collision”[54].
The difference between man and animal, and the fact that animals have instincts
and not passions, clearly links passion to man and to freedom. In this sense,
only the reasonable man can be subject to the disease of the will and to the
passion, which is an element of opposition and natural necessity, as opposed to
the freedom of the moral law.
Now, returning to the concept of imputability, Kant
links the problem in the Metaphysics of
morals to the concept of person. Kant defines the person as: “a subject
whose actions can be imputed to him. Moral personality is therefore nothing
other than the freedom of a rational being under moral laws (whereas
psychological personality is merely the capacity for being conscious of one’s
identity in different conditions of one’s existence). From this it follows that
a person is subject to no other laws than those he gives to himself.”[55]
The concept of person has relevance both in the domain of law and in that of ethics,
through the relation with the notions of “obligation”, “imputation”, “duty”,
“freedom” and “law”. The originality of Kant’s reflection on the concept of
“person” derives from its link with the Wolffian heritage: in Wolff, therefore,
the moral or spiritual man, distinct from the merely carnal man, is the subject
of rights and obligations; as such, in the wake of Grotius and Locke, man is a
person, because he carries out imputable actions and, as a person, he is free
because imputability entails reference to a dimension further than that of
natural causality. In Kant, we can find an analogous intertwining between the
concepts of person, freedom and imputability: however, each of these concepts,
and therefore also the whole, must be placed in the new argumentative horizon
opened by the categorical imperative, which involves the a priori foundation of
obligation. In Kant, in fact, the imputability of actions refers to the
criterion of the interior duty to man: thus it emerges that the juridical
capacity of the Kantian person, which is not reducible simply to a habilitas, as in Wolff, and the very
fact of “being a person” is no longer defined in Kant from the point of view of
a generally understood will, but on the basis of a “pure possible will”.
Imputation is, then: “(imputatio) in
the moral sense is a judgment by which someone is regarded as the author (causa libera) of an action, which is
then called a deed (factum) and stands under law.”[56]
In this conception, the human person appears to be endowed with moral
conscience (Gewissen) and awareness (Bewusstein), unlike things (“is that to
which nothing can be imputed”), animals or, as we have seen, the insane or
mentally ill. In order to be imputed, in fact, the action must be free and it
is precisely for this reason that in the case of a drunk or a maniac the
actions can be ascribed to the two subjects but it is not possible to impute
them to these people. In Kant, therefore, there is the conception that freedom
of action and the moral law proceed together in imputation. When the action is
not free, for whatever reason, according to Kant it cannot be imputed, but only
ascribed to the subject who performs it.
To conclude the discourse on imputability, we now
refer to the theme of the fragility of human nature, expressed by Kant in the
expected “degrees” of imputation. In the Lectures
on Ethics, Kant argues that the degrees of imputation depend on the degrees
of freedom. The subjective conditions of freedom are the capacity to act, that
is, the knowledge of the motive and object of the action. In the absence of
these conditions, the charge does not take place. Kant offers the example of
the child and the drunkard. Kant also believes that the greater are the
impediments (including psychological and related to freedom and will), the less
free the action. He who kills out of jealousy and he who steals out of hunger
have different appetites: an appetite of nature and an appetite of greed. Kant
precisely distinguishes between the two, condemning the latter. Another reason
for the reduction of imputability is the weakness [Schwäche] and the frailty [Gebrechlichkeit]
of human nature. The sentence becomes less applicable when there is a weakness
of human nature: in that case the person who is fragile does not have the moral
goodness to perform an action which is adequate to the law. In Kant the
fragility and the weakness of human nature are important concepts, like radical
evil. In fact, in man there can be both the absence of positive good and the
presence of positive evil, as a natural tendency to evil. According to Kant, fragilitas and human infirmitas can be evaluated only in
others and in their actions, and the pragmatic judge and legislator has the
duty to consider these two concepts when judging subjects who are also men. In
this sense, Kantian legal theory is not only connected to the concept of
personality and imputation but also to other dimensions of human subjectivity,
which is conceived in a structured way. The Kantian concept of imputability
explains the action of a free subject, the behavior of a fragile or weak man,
the crime of a delinquent. In the case of mental illness, where it is not
possible to consider a concept of imputability, the challenge for the Kantian
interpretation is the study of an another conception of subjectivity, in
addition to that of personality.
Bibliography
Borges, M. (2004) What
Can Kant Teach Us about Emotion?,
Journal of Philosophy, 101; pp. 140
– 58.
Frierson, P. (2009), Kant on Mental Disorder, Journal of History of Psychiatry, 20 (03),
pp. 1 – 23.
Kant, I. (2006), Anthropology from a Pragmatic
Point of view, ed. by R. B. Louden, Cambridge
Kant, I. (2002), Critique
of Practical Reason, ed., tr. by W. S. Pluhar, intr. by S. Engstrom,
Cambridge
Kant, I. (1987), Critique
of Judgment, ed., tr., by W. S. Pluhar; M. J. Gregor, Cambridge
Kant, I. (1998), Critique
of Pure Reason, ed. by P. Guyer, A. W. Wood, Cambridge
Kant, I. (2003), Dreams
of a Spirit-Seer, tr. by Gregory R. Johnson, Swedenborg Foundation
Publishers
Kant, I. (2012), Lectures on Anthropology, ed.
by A. Wood, R. Louden, Cambridge
Kant, I. (1997), Lectures
on Ethics, ed. by P. Heath – J.B. Scheenwind, Cambridge
Kant, I. (1996), The
Metaphysics of Morals, ed. by M. Gregor, R. J. Sullivan, Cambridge, 1996.
Kant, I. (1996), The
Conflict of Faculties, ed. by Allen W. Wood, Cambridge
Frierson, P. (2014), Kant’s Empirical Psychology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Foucault, M. (1965), Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason,
New York, Vintage
Hufeland, C. W. H. (1995), Die Kunst, das menschliche Leben zu verlängern, Frankfurt a. M. –
Leipzing.
Marianetti,
M. (1999), Vivere, invecchiare ed essere
vecchi. Kant e Christoph Wilhelm Hufeland, Istituti Editoriali e
Poligrafici Internazionali, Pisa – Roma.
Marino, L. (1994),
Soemmering, Kant and the Organ of Soul, in Romanticism in Science. Science in Europe, 1790 – 1840, ed. by S.
Poggi, M. Bossi, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp.127 - 142.
Meo,
O. (1982), La malattia mentale in Kant, Tilgher,
Genova
Rogerson, Kenneth F. (2008), The Problem of Free Harmony in Kant’s Aesthetics, State University
of New York Pres
Sömmering, S.T. (1796), Über das Organ der Seele, Nicolovius, Königsberg.
Von
Engelhardt, D. (2003), Il dialogo fra
medicina e filosofia in Kant nel contesto storico, in Kant e il conflitto delle facoltà. Ermeneutica, progresso storico,
medicina, ed. by C. Bertani e M. A. Pranteda, il Mulino, pp. 253 – 265.
Zammito, J. (2002), Kant, Herder, and the Birth of Anthropology, University of Chicago
Press
·
Research Fellow at Istituto Italiano per gli Studi filosofici - I.I.S.F.
(Naples, Italy); ilaria.ferrara@edu.unito.it
[1] On this point, Frierson, P. (2009), Kant on Mental Disorder, Journal of History
of Psychiatry, 20 (03), pp. 1 – 23.
[2] To find out more see also, Meo, O.
(1982), La malattia mentale in Kant, Tilgher,
Genova.
[3]For example, Kant indicates that the
reading of novels can become a cause of dementia
by making distraction habitual, so avoiding novels is a way to help ward off
dementia. He also proposes art and culture as ways of refining feeling and
thereby treating affects.
[4]See also Zammito, J. (2002), Kant, Herder, and the Birth of Anthropology,
University of Chicago Press, p. 250.
[5] To study the dialogue between medicine and philosophy, see also Von Engelhardt, D. (2003), Il dialogo fra medicina e filosofia in Kant nel contesto storico, in Kant e il conflitto delle facoltà. Ermeneutica, progresso storico, medicina, ed. by C. Bertani e M. A. Pranteda, il Mulino, pp. 253 – 265.
[6] Kant, I. (1996), The Conflict of Faculties, ed. by Allen
W. Wood, Cambridge.
[7] See also Marino L. (1994), Soemmering, Kant and the Organ of Soul,
in Romanticism in Science. Science in Europe,
1790 – 1840, ed. by S. Poggi, M. Bossi, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic
Publishers, pp.127 - 142.
[8] Sömmering, S.T. (1796), Über das Organ der Seele, Nicolovius,
Königsberg.
[9] Hufeland, C. W. H. (1995), Die Kunst, das menschliche Leben zu verlängern,
Frankfurt a. M. – Leipzing.
[10] On the concept of the conservation of life as an moral ideal, see Marianetti, M. (1999), Vivere, invecchiare ed essere vecchi. Kant e Christoph Wilhelm Hufeland, Istituti Editoriali e Poligrafici Internazionali, Pisa – Roma.
[11] Kant, I. (2007), Essay on Maladies of the Head, ed. by G. Zöller, R. Louden, tr. H.
Wilson, Cambridge.
[12] Kant, I. (2006), Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of view,
ed. by R. Louden, Cambridge.
[13] Kant, I. (2012), Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful
and Sublime, ed. by. P. Frierson, P. Guyer, Cambridge.
[14] Kant, I. (2003), Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, tr. by Gregory
R. Johnson, Swedenborg Foundation Publishers.
[15] An interesting point of view on the
theme is given by Foucault, M. (1965), Madness
and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason, New York, Vintage.
[16]For an interpretation of society as
an artificial machine and its liberation in an aesthetic and philosophical
sense, see also Schiller, On the
Aesthetic Education of Man in a Series of Letters. Here, Schiller elaborates
a theory of harmonious activity in which a balance or equipoise is maintained.
In particular, starting from Kant and Rousseau, Schiller believes in elevating
human potential through the arts for the development of free citizens of the Republic,
using the model of the French Revolution.
[17] Kant, I. (1998), Critique of Pure Reason, ed. by P. Guyer, A. W. Wood, Cambridge.
[18] Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of view, p. 110
[19]For the problem of a “empirical
psychology” in Kantian philosophy see Frierson, P. (2014), Kant’s Empirical Psychology, Cambridge.
[20]Anthropology,
p. 20.
[21]Anthropology,
p. 109.
[22]For a good reconstruction of the
defects of the faculty and the problem of the connection between disease and
epistemology, see also Frierson, P. Kant
on Mental Disorder (2009).
[23]Anthropology,
p. 108.
[24]Anthropology,
p. 113.
[25] The term nihilism is famous in Nietzsche’s philosophy but in this context it
is useful to understand the particular form of “gnoseological solipsism” of the
mentally ill in Kantian philosophy.
[26] This issue obviously concerns the
epistemological status of empirical psychology which, for Kant, is not an exact
science like mathematics and physics. Empirical psychology deals with an
empirical, changeable and non-deducible object starting from a formal rule.
Kantian empirical psychology has a small place in its critical system and is
partially replaced by anthropology, which is not a formally rigorous science (einer förmlichen Wissenschaft).
[27] This is also problematic in B.
Russell’s philosophical work. Beyond the distinctions between analytic and
synthetic, logic is autonomous and, as he says in the “Introduction to
mathematical philosophy”, it is a question of giving a new meaning to the
principle according to which truths are analytic (a new meaning because the
principle of non-contradiction). On the other hand, he assumes, in a Leibnizian
way (like Gödel), that we have an intuitive knowledge both of the truths of
mathematics and of factual truths (for example, cogito or apperception fall
into the latter species). In later texts, between 1913 and 1914, he tries to
sketch a theory of non-dualistic knowledge, whereby the truths of mathematics
and logic are precisely "hard data" and that their criterion is finally
a sort of psychological “evidence”. In fact, Leibniz also argues that the type
of evidence of the truths of reason cannot be compared with those of fact, and
says that for the latter we need a logic of verisimilitude.
[28] The discourse on the private dimension
of illness can also be explained through the aesthetic perspective of the Critique of Judgment, in which Kant
separates the public judgment on the beautiful from the private judgment on the
pleasant. Judgments about the agreeable are private because they cannot be
communicated, as they show something that pleases the senses and subjective
sensations; judgments about what is beautiful show a very particular claim to
subjective universality. In the first case, i.e. in the judgments on the
agreeable, that which pleases remains on a private level of knowledge, and the
content is not communicable, in the same way in which mental illnesses link the
subject to a form of erroneous and prejudicial reasoning, devoid of any
foundation in reality. In the judgment of the agreeable, however, there will be
a judgment of perception, that is, a judgment based on private sensations,
which is not communicable to others, but which they can still understand
starting from the same system of sensible perception. As for the judgments that
the patient bases on what he believes to be true and real, we speak instead of
a completely altered state of the use of the faculties, in which logical
prejudice is understood at its highest degree. Some diseases, in fact, seem to
oppose the structure of "I think" as they not only introduce a
private sense of logic but also they split of one personality into many
different personalities.
[29] See also, Kenneth F. Rogerson
(2008), The Problem of Free Harmony in
Kant’s Aesthetics, State University of New York Press.
[30] I. Kant, Vorlesung über Philosophischen Enzyklopädie (1775), Ak XXIX1,
25.
[31] The discourse could also be
inserted into the more general problem of obscure
representations [Anthropology, §
5] between sensibility and the faculty of understanding.
[32]I. Kant, Anthropology, p. 111.
[33]Ibidem
[34]Anthropology,
p. 114.
[35] I. Kant, Anthropology, p. 149.
[36] I. Kant (2002), Critique of Practical Reason, ed., tr.
by W. S. Pluhar, intr. by S. Engstrom, Cambridge.
[37] Anthropology, p. 149.
[38]I. Kant (2012), Lectures on
Anthropology, ed. by A. Wood, R. Louden, Cambridge, p. 142.
[39]For this questions, see also the
concept of akrasia. The Aristotelian notion of akrasia has been
re-enacted by Anglophone philosophy, to indicate an inconsistent practice with
respect to recognized and proclaimed values (Chapell, 1995; MacIntyre, 1988).
To focus on it we consider four different levels concerning ethical discourse
and actual action. They are: objective norms (prescriptive level); the values
or principles of the subject (axiological level); beliefs (preferential
level); intentions (teleological or intentional level). With regard to the
relationships between them, we note that: the objective norms and intentions of
the subject are not identified; the relationship between the objective norms
and the values or principles of the subject is mediated by beliefs. Regarding
beliefs, akrasia presupposes that in addition to distinguishing between the
objective level of the obligation and the subjective level of beliefs, we must
also distinguish what the subject considers positive for himself, from what he
considers positive in and of himself. The distinction between axiological
beliefs and preferential beliefs is important to explain the akrasia and the
bases of a theory of will and action. This in order to constitute a bridge
between the action plan, closely linked to the intentional and the epistemic
one of the subject's preferential beliefs and, in a mediated and variable form,
also that of his axiological beliefs.
[40]Anthropology, p. 152.
[41]Anthropology,
p. 149.
[42]Anthropology,
p. 149.
[43]Anthropology,
p. 165.
[44]Anthropology,
p. 166.
[45]Anthropology,
p. 165.
[46] See also, Borges, M. (2004) “What
Can Kant Teach Us about Emotion?”, Journal of
Philosophy 101: 140 – 58.
[47] Anthropology, p. 166.
[48] Kant, I. (1997) Lectures on Ethics, ed. by P. Heath – J.B. Scheenwind, Cambridge,
1997, p. 80.
[49] Kant, I. (1996), The Metaphysics of Morals, ed. by M.
Gregor, R. J. Sullivan, Cambridge, 1996.
[50] See also, Bratman, M. (1979)
“Practical reasoning and Weakness of the Will”, Nous 13; 153- 71.
[51] The Kantian perspective presented
in §48 of Anthropology, where the
problem of the protection of the
mentally ill is discussed, seems to consider the patient without personality.
[52] Anthropology, p. 166.
[53] Ibidem
[54] Anthropology, p. 169.
[55] The Metaphysics of
Morals, p. 50.
[56] The Metaphysics of
Morals, p. 53.