Kant on Eating and Drinking
Maria Borges·
Universidade Federal de Santa Catarina, Brasil
Abstract
In this paper I analyze Kant’s ideas about eating and
drinking. First, I show that gluttony and drunkenness are considered ways to
oppose to the duty to oneself as an animal being. Second, I claim that for Kant
there is a healthy way of having meals, which consists in eating together with
friends. Then I indicate that Kant accepts that one can drink at dinner parties
but has to avoid drinks that lead to drunkenness and unsocial behavior. In this
sense, he draws a classification of the various kinds of alcoholic drinks,
according to their potential harm. Afterwards, I illustrate how Kant’s own
intimate life was a daily practice of his thoughts on dietetic conceptions and on
what is better for digestion and health. To conclude, I mention the idea of a philosopher’s
medicine of the body and why a strict diet should be avoided.
Key words
eat, drink, Kant, medicine, digestion
What is the
importance of Kant’s view on eating and drinking?
Why should we care
about this discussion on Kant vis-à-vis food or drink? Does it have any relation
with his practical philosophy? Or does it have only biographical relevance? Does
Kant’s view still have any relevance for us today? Is it based on sound
medicine? Should his dietetical advice be followed nowadays?
In
this paper I show that Kant’s remarks about the excessive use of food and drink
have an importance concerning his doctrine of virtue. Gluttony and drunkenness
are considered vices because they are against the duties to oneself as animal
being related to the preservation of one’s body.
Kant’s vision about eating and
drinking also has an importance regarding the value of socialization in meals,
that may lead to the improvement of social interaction and virtue. Also, his
view about which foods and drinks we are to have is related to medical views.
Although some are obsolete, the advice for moderation is still a valuable principle
to keep one’s health.
Gluttony, drunkenness,
and the duties to oneself
In the §5 of the Doctrine of Virtue, Kant claims that the
human being has a duty to oneself as an animal being, that consists in preserving
oneself in one’s animal nature. There are many different ways of acting against
this duty. One is to commit suicide; another one is mutilating oneself.
Mutilation can be material or formal. Material mutilation is to deprive oneself
of an organic part, such as the castration of singers or selling a tooth to be
transplanted in another’s mouth. However, there are some circumstances under
which one can cut a part of one’s body and it would not be considered
mutilation. Kant claims that to “have a dead or diseased organ amputated when
it endangers one’s life, or to have something cut off that is a part but not an
organ of the body, for example, one’s hair, cannot be counted as a crime
against one’s own person” (TL, AA 6: 423). To cut off a part of the body that
is not an organ, such as hair or nails, does not count as mutilation. Also, it
is not mutilation to amputate an organ that can prevent the death of the sick person.
There is another form of mutilation,
a formal one, that consists in depriving oneself “of one’s capacity for the
natural (and so indirectly for the moral) use of one’s powers” (TL, AA 6: 421).
Kant classifies excessive drinking and eating as forms of formal mutilation:
Brutish
excess in the use of food and drink is misuse of the means of nourishment that
restricts or exhausts our capacity to use them intelligently. Drunkenness and
gluttony are the vices that come under this heading. A human being who is drunk
is like a mere animal, not to be treated as a human being. When stuffed with
food he is in a condition in which he is incapacitated, for a time, for actions
that would require him to use his powers with skill and deliberation. It is
obvious that putting oneself in such a state violates a duty to oneself (TL, AA
6: 427).
Although Kant does
not specify how much of food and drink count as gluttony and drunkenness, both are
considered morally wrong. Excess in eating is below human dignity, since it is
a passive condition that approaches the enjoyment of cattle, without any
arousal of the imagination:
Gluttony
is even lower than that animal enjoyment of the senses, since it only lulls the
senses into a passive condition and, unlike drunkenness, does not even arouse
imagination to an active play of representation; so it approaches even more
closely the enjoyment of cattle (TL, AA 6: 427)
Drunkenness is
considered morally wrong. Even if the act of getting drunk is a free act, it is
against the consistency of freedom, because it prevents the use of the capacity
to make further choices. Guyer explains the Kantian meaning of this
consistence:
One
thing it seems to mean is that I must make free choices on particular occasions
in a way that preserves and promotes my ability to make and carry out further
free choices on other occasions. To use some Kant’s characteristic examples,
particular decisions to commit suicide or get drunk considered by themselves
would certainly be free choices - instances of setting myself “any end
whatsoever” – but they would not be consistent with preserving and promoting my
capacity to make and carry out further free choices (GUYER 2006, p. 187).
Even if committing
suicide and getting drunk seem to be acts of extreme freedom, they lead to the
opposite: the restriction of the use of one’s capacity to act freely.
The importance of
a meal in a good company
In Anthropology, Kant claims that “the good
living that still seems to harmonize best with true humanity is a good meal in
good company” (Anth, AA 7: 278). At a dinner party, people enjoy not only food
and drinks, but mutual company. Although there is this general idea that Kant
was a lonely man, and even a misanthrope, his comments on the importance of
banquets shows the opposite:
Eating
alone (solipsismus convictorii) is
unhealthy for a scholar who philosophizes; it is not restauration but
exhaustion (especially if it becomes solitary feasting); fatiguing work rather than a stimulating play of
thoughts. The savouring human being
who weakens himself in thought during his solitary meal gradually loses his sprightliness
which, on the other hand, he would have gained if a table companion with
alternative ideas had offered stimulation through new material which he himself
had not been able to track down (Anth, AA 7: 280).
Solitary meals debilitate men because they lack the
stimulation of a lively discussion at the table. In accepting this important feature
of a social meal, Kant asks if one can be justified in accepting the invitation
for a banquet, since it is also an invitation to the use of wine, a drink that “enlivens
the company conversation and in so doing makes them speak more freely” (TL, AA 6:428).
Although
a banquet is a formal invitation to excess in both food and drink, there is
still something in it that aims at a moral end, beyond mere physical well-being:
it brings a number of people together for a long time to converse with one
another. And yet the very number of guests (if, as Chesterfield says, it
exceeds the number of the muses) allows for only a little conversation (with
those sitting next to one); and so the arrangement is at variance with that end,
while the banquet remains a temptation to something immoral, namely
intemperance, which is a violation of one’s duty to oneself- not to mention the
physical harm of overindulgence, which could perhaps be cured by a doctor (TL, AA
6: 428).
A banquet may be an
invitation to intemperance, but at the same time it is an occasion for people
to get along and have social intercourse, which is a good way to develop social
virtues. There remains a casuistic question, if one should or not accept these
invitations: “How far does one’s moral authorization to accept these
invitations extend?” (TL, AA 6: 428). Should we accept or not the invitation
for the dinner parties and consequently the temptation to excess in food and
alcoholic beverages? It is not clear if Kant would recommend temperance in eating
during the banquets, but he would certainly advise to drink but not to get drunk,
because as one reads in Anthropology: “Drunkenness is the unnatural
condition of inability to order one´s sense representation according to the laws
of experience, provided that the condition is the effect of an excessive
consumption of drink” (Anth, AA 7:166).
The classification
of drinks
Is Kant
criticizing the excess of drinking or the consumption of any alcoholic
beverage? In Anthropology, he
makes a distinction among the many beverages: “All silent intoxication has
something shameful in it; that is, intoxication that does not enliven
sociability and the reciprocal communication of thoughts – of which opium and
brandy are examples” (Anth, AA 7:170).
Here
it seems that consumption of spirits and drinks that derive from narcotics such
as opium deserves the strongest reprobation. In Doctrine of Virtue, when
referring to the vice of drunkenness, he claims that this debasement, “below even
the nature of an animal, is usually brought about by fermented drinks, but they
can also result from narcotics, such as opium and other vegetable products” (TL,
AA 6: 427). These drinks are not welcome, because while they are seductive and
make men dream that they are happy for a moment, they are also followed by a
bodily and mental weakness, and in the case of narcotics, by addiction.
While he is undoubtedly critical of
the use of narcotics and fermented drinks, the consumption of wine is the
object of a certain doubt, since it is consumed at dinner parties that have the
end of bringing about moral sociability: “The use of opium and spirits for
enjoyment is closer to be a base act than the use of wine, since they make the
user silent, reticent and withdrawn by the dreamy euphoria they induce. They
are therefore permitted only as medicines” (TL, AA 6: 428).
The acceptance of alcoholic beverages
is based on their potential for bringing about social interaction. If we were
to approve some sort of intoxication, be it for the purpose of sociability:
Wine,
which merely stimulates, and beer, which is more nourishing and satisfying like
a food, serve as social intoxication; but with the difference that
drinking-bouts with beer make guests dreamier and more withdrawn, whereas at a
wine party the guests are cheerful, boisterous, talkative, and witty (Anth, AA
7:170).
Between wine and
beer, Kant prefers the use of wine, not only because it fosters social
interaction, but also because it could strengthen virtue. At least in two
texts, Kant cites Horace’s praise to Cato, virtus eius incaluit mero, “his
virtue was strengthened by wine”. (TL, AA 6: 428, Anth, AA 7: 171) Apparently,
he admits that could be the case.
In her article “The ultimate Kantian
experience: Kant on dinner parties”, Alix Cohen introduces a classification of
drinks and drugs according to their relation to sociability and virtue. Wine is the first in the rank, because it
induces merriness and is also good to virtue. Beer is in the second rank, because,
while it is an intoxication that helps social interaction, it induces
impoliteness; it is good for conversation, but bad for virtuous sociability.
The worst are opium, brandy and spirits, because they “induce silence,
reticence, stultifying and dreamy euphoria. Thus, they contravene sociability
and conversation” (COHEN 2008, p. 318).
According to Wasianski, Kant was
even more critical to beer, which he considered a “slow, but mortal drink”: “he
was a declared enemy of this drink, and, when a man died in the force of ages,
he used to say: ‘undoubtedly, he was a beer drinker” (WASIANSKI 1985, p. 121).
The intimate Kant
Kant not only defended the
importance of a good meal in a good company, he also lived according to this
conception, always avoiding having his meal alone. According to Jachmann,[1]
until the age of 73, Kant had lunch at a hotel, where many important people of
the Konigsberg society used to join him. He was also invited to private lunches
by members of the Prussian government, as well as bankers and art dealers: M
von Schroetter, minister of the State; Comte Henckel von Donnersmark, the General
Von Brunneck, the Duque of Holsteinbeck, the Comte of Kayserling, the bank director
Ruffman; the art dealer Motherby. (JACHMANN 1985, p. 44).[2]
After the age of 73, Kant finally moved
to a house of his own and usually invited a certain number of hosts to lunch,
which was the only meal Kant used to have on a daily basis. The lunch followed
the rules concerning the number of guests Kant made explicit in Anthropology:
more than the number of graces and less of the number of muses. He also tried
to have interesting but light conversation during the meal, and according to his
former student Wasianski they never talked about his Critiques. The
subjects of conversation varied from physiology, medicine, the life and habits
of the people, chemistry, natural history and also politics. These gatherings
followed the idea of a cultivation that Kant considered important for the
spirit of Enlightenment. Also, he invited many different members of what we
could call the Enlightenment society: professors, students, doctors, State
employees, cultivated salesmen (WASIANSKI 1985, p.65).
The lunch’s menu was composed by a three-course
meal, cheese, butter, and dessert. The meal was accompanied by wine, usually a
Medoc, but sometimes he also had white wine, because the red one was too astringent
for him (JACHMANN, 1985, p. 47). The first course was usually a fish plate and
Kant’s favorite was cod. He was so fond of a good meal to the point that his
friend Hippel once told him that he should write a “Critique of cooking” (BOROWSKI
1985, p. 17). For him, one of the virtues of women was to prepare a good dinner
to the point that he once said that “a man, even if he is a painter or a poet,
would not be happy if his wife offer him a poem or a painting instead of a
dinner” (JACHMANN, 1985, p.48). This was considered a sexist view, even by
women of the 18th century.
Digestion, food,
and health
It is easy to
understand that alcohol drinks could lead to a lack of control of one’s own
mind and then create the conditions for the weakness of the will, but how could
gluttony be a moral problem? Although it can certainly lead to diseases and to the
need to ask for a doctor’s help, it is unclear how this could have a moral importance.
Although gluttony is considered a
vice related to a duty to oneself as an animal being, not overeating seems also
to be related to Kant’s concerns about health, besides moral concerns.
He was very interested in medicine
and was aware of some medical theories of his time, according to which to be
healthy is a consequence of the equilibrium of the vital forces. Besides
reading the news about discoveries in medicine, Kant has his own thoughts about
the correct way to attain this equilibrium. The fact that he used to have only
one meal a day is probably an important part of his own dietetic program.
Another recommendation of this discipline was not to sleep after a huge meal, in
order to avoid some digestion problems. The advice not to discuss hard subjects
during the meal, besides the rules of etiquette, also responded to a health
concern: to aid digestion. This purpose can be seen in the proposed three
stages of a meal: narration, arguing, digestion. In the first one, people should talk about light
subjects, such as the news of the days. In the second part, the party becomes livelier
and people dispute over many subjects.
Lively discussion has also a
physiological purpose, as it helps to stir up the appetite for food and drink:
“a dispute arises that which stirs up the appetite for food and drink and also
makes the appetite wholesome in proportion to the liveliness of this dispute
and the participation on it” (Anth, AA 7: 280). After eating, mild and witty conversation
should take place because arguing would take the energy that should be used for
digestion:
And
so, the meal ends with laughter, which, if it is loud and good-natured, has
actually been determined by nature to help the stomach in the digestive process
through the movement of the diaphragm and intestines, thus promoting physical well-being
(Anth, AA 7: 281).
While talking
about the affects that promote health mechanically Kant gives more details of
the physiological process involved in laughing (Anth, AA 7: 262): the exhaling
of air in laugher “strengthens the feeling of vital force through the wholesome
exercise of the diaphragm” and is “a shaking of muscles involved in digestion”,
in this way promoting health “far better than the physician’s wisdom would do”.
Also, for elderly people, laughing is a healthful exercise. In comparing young
people’s preference for drama and old people’s preference for comedy and
burlesque, Kant explains why they do not appreciate the distressing and
terrifying impressions of a drama:
On
the other hand, with old people these impressions are not so easily blotted
out, and they cannot bring back the cheerful mood in themselves so easily. By
his antic a nimble-witted harlequin produces a beneficial shaking of their diaphragm
and intestines, by which their appetite for the ensuing social supper is whetted
and thrives as a result of the lively conversation (Anth, AA 7: 263).
Besides laughing,
there are other affects by which nature promotes health mechanically. Crying and
anger are among these affects that can help digestion:
Anger
is also a fairly reliable aid to digestion, if one can scold freely (without
fear of resistance), and many a housewife has no other emotional exercise than
the scolding of her children and servants. Now if the children and servants
only submit to it, an agreeable tiredness of the vital force spreads itself
uniformly through her body; however, this remedy is not without its dangers,
since she fears resistance by these members of the household (Anth, AA 7:261).
Kant was very
concerned with digestion, not only theoretically, but also in his daily life. According
to Jachmann, “he thought it was important to attain an old age, and he had a
list of the older people in Konigsberg and he was happy to advance in that
list” (JACHMANN 1985, p. 48). In one of their last meetings, Kant told his
secretary that he was very proud of what he had done to his body and “that he placed
great value on what he considered a feat: having managed to maintain his health
and vigor” (JACHMANN 1985, p. 51). He was extremely interested in staying
healthy and having a good digestion was an important part of that. Besides
moderation in eating, he also regularly took some pills of aloes, a spoon of cinchona tincture, and a small glass of Rhum in the
morning, although these last two ended up having bad outcomes. The cinchona
tincture made his pulse irregular and the Rhum gave him heartburn.
Kant had a strict routine. He woke up every day
at 5 am, had breakfast until 7 am, that consisted only of two cups of tea. After
that, he gave courses at the University or at home. Afterwards, he worked until
12:45 in his office. He received his guests at 1 pm for lunch, and this
gathering could go on until 4 or 5 pm. After lunch, he used to take a one-hour
walk along the same street every day and to come home to read or prepare his
courses until 10 pm, when he went to sleep. This discipline and his dietetic
concerns seemed to have led Kant to attain the surprising age of 80, in a time
when the expectancy of life was around 37 years old, and to remain active until
nearly his last year.
In his daily routine we can find an
answer to the proper use of alcoholic beverages. It is not against virtue to
drink wine with moderation and use it to enliven a conversation during a meal.
The criticism seems to be directed to other beverages, such as beer, besides the
use of alcohol for the purpose of a lonely drunkenness.
The philosopher’s
medicine of the body
In the speech Kant
gave in the completion of his term as a Rector of the University of Konigsberg,
he claims that the philosopher can have a function in treating the body through
reason. While “the doctor’s business is to help the ailing mind by caring for
the body; the philosopher’s is to assist the afflicted body by a mental regimen”
(Rektoratsrede, AA 15: 939). One of the topics of this speech is how the powers
of the mind could help to promote health, in particular a good digestion. Kant claims
that “everyone knows how we can promote digestion by the emotions stirred in
friendly but lively conversation, or by turning away from our meditations
during dinner” (Rektoratsrede, AA 15: 940).
He advises that people should free
their minds from any concerns and that conversation should be an enthusiastic one:
It
is healthful for the body when, at dinner, the mind is not only free from care
but disposed to merriment and turned away from concentrating on any one
subject. What best serves the body is conversation, amiable discussion,
especially mirth breaking into hearty laughter. Here the mind exerts most
strongly its force in moving the body (Rektoratsrede, AA 15: 940).
In this speech, he
calls attention to the aspects underscored in Anthropology, as well as in
Doctrine of Virtue: a meal should encompass a light discussion and end up
with a good laugher. This is not only good for the spirit, but it helps to
promote health. And again, he mentions that to help the function of the body,
it is not advisable to eat alone in a quiet mood, but to have a lively conversation
with friends:
It
is not only when the mind is free from care and serene that it aids the vital
functions of the body, but also when it is stirred up, at dinner, by the sport
and jests of conversation- when, to enliven the gathering, the guests enter
into a contest, and the enthusiasm and exertion of the conversationalists rises
to the limits of an affect (Rektoratsrede, AA 15: 949)
The interaction of
people at dinner or lunch increases the vital forces of the body by the
excitement of the mind. Among the doctors of his time, Kant expressed his
partiality for the system of John Brown, the Scottish doctor, whose methods,
according to Mary Gregor, “are said to have killed more people than the French
Revolution and the Napoleonic wars combined (including its founder, who died of
an overdose of his favorite remedies, opium and whisky)” (GREGOR 1992, p.191).
According to John Brown, life is a forced state, resulting from the presence of
exciting powers. If the exciting powers are withdrawn, the human being dies.
Following this principle, diseases are classified between sthenic and asthenic
diseases, the first ones resulting from the excess of excitement, the second,
due to deficient excitement.
Having Brown’s system in mind, Kant
will not advice strict temperance while eating. Even though Kant criticizes
gluttony, he was not for a strict diet that keeps one always hungry: “It is true,
he says, that the sort of intemperance that indulges the body alone is most to
be avoided, and Horace in particular says: the body burdened with yesterday vices…
But wisdom does not require us to cheat ourselves, in step motherly fashion,
and waste away by frugality” (Rektoratsrede, AA 15: 950).
Whilst people should void gluttony, Kant
stresses the importance of having a proper meal, although this could cause some
stomach discomforts. Even if people have digestion problems, Kant advise them
to eat for the purpose of not weakening the forces of the body: “so it is
particularly relevant that someone can become, as it were, intemperate on
fasting, because of certain discomforts that generally go along with a full
stomach” (Rektoratsrede, AA 15: 942). Kant also had some discomforts related to
digestion, according to his biographers. However, his opinion is that one has
to tolerate these digestive problems, without lessening the right amount of
food: “my opinion”, he says, “is that one should eat to satiety at least once a
day, and put up with the resulting discomfort until the body’s strength has
increased” (Rektoratsrede, AA 15:942).
Eating less than one needs is worse for
the body than overeating. The body’s balance cannot be attained by an
abstemiousness that makes one always hungry and sub-nourished:
So
the imminent philosopher Mendelssohn was forced to observe strict temperance
because of the many bodily infirmities from which he suffered. But, as we have
heard, in trying to keep his mind in good shape for his studies, he went beyond
temperance to such abstemiousness that he kept himself always hungry, so as to
avoid the slight and usually transitory discomforts of the stomach that follow
a proper meal (Rektoratsrede, AA 15: 950).
Mendelssohn died
in 1786. The question of what caused his death was debated in the newspapers of
Berlin and Hamburg. According to Mary Gregor, some blamed Jacobi for that,
because he has criticized Lessing for being an atheist, mocker and hypocrite, and
made some unprincipled use of Lessing comments on Spinoza. Mendelssohn felt
obliged to refute the attack on his friend: “Mendelssohn produced his reply
quickly, so as to erase the impression Jacobi had made, and the strain so
weakened him that he died of a cold he caught while delivering his reply to the
publisher” (Gregor 1992, p.205).
Kant was aware of this debate, but
he did not impute his death to any philosophical discussion, no matter how unkind:
Eulogizers
of that great man Mendelssohn put the blame for his death on one or another of
the learned man who got him involved in a dispute with them. In my judgement,
however, no one should be accused of such an atrocious crime. What was at fault
was, rather, the very way of life of that much-lamented man (Rektoratsrede, AA
15: 942)
Kant finally attributed
the death of Moses Mendelssohn to a mistake in his diet, because he followed a
diet based on strict temperance and abstemiousness: “By this, however, he so
weakened the forces of his body, that the sort of every-day injury, that would
hardly affect someone properly nourished, shattered and killed that
much-lamented man, exhausted by excessive temperance” (Rektoratsrede, AA 15: 951).
It is important to consider that, against excesses,
Kant defends moderation, and in the case of food he rejects fasting,
considering that satiety is preferable at least at one meal a day, as was his
habit.
Kant’s
remarks inform us about his philosophy more generally in interesting ways and
help us rethinking the moral value of consumption today. He points to a wise
use of food and drink, that correctly nourishes the body, without the excess of
consumption, and prevent us to follow a diet that will not give enough nutrients
for the body.
Bibliography
Borowski,
L. E. (1985), “Description de la vie et du caractére d’Emmanuel Kant”, in: Mistler,
J. (org.), Kant Intime, Bernard Grasset, France.
Cohen, A. (2008), “Kant ultimate experience: Kant on
dinner parties”, History of philosophy
quarterly, 25 (4), pp. 315-336
Gregor,
M. (1992), “Introduction to On Philosophers of the body”, in: Kant, I., Kant’s
latin writings: translation, commentaries, and notes, Lang, USA.
Guyer, P. (2006),
Kant, Routledge, USA.
Jachman, R. B. (1985).
“Emmanuel Kant raconté dans des lettres a un ami“, in: Mistler, J. (org.), Kant
Intime, Bernard Grasset, France.
Kant, I., Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht.
Kants gesammelte Schriften. Band 7 (Königlich Preussischen Akademie der
Wissenschaften, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1900-
Kant, I., Rektoratsrede.
Kants gesammelte Schriften. Band 15 (Königlich Preussischen Akademie der
Wissenschaften, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1900-
Kant, I., Die Metaphysik der Sitten. Tugendlehre.
Kants gesammelte Schriften. Band 6 (Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften,
Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1900-
Kant,
I. (1992), Kant’s latin writings: translation, commentaries, and notes,
Lang,USA.
Mistler,
J. (org.) (1985), Kant Intime, Bernard Grasset, France.
Wasianki,
E. A. (1985), “Emmanuel Kant dans ses dernières années“. in: Mistler, J. (org.),
Kant Intime, Bernard Grasset, France.
· Professor of Philosophy at the UFSC (Brazil). E-mail
for contact: mariaborges@yahoo.com
[1] Reinhold Bernhard Jachmann was director of the
provincial school of Conradino auf Jenkau, near Konigsberg. He was a student of
Kant and his secretary from 1784 to 1794. Kant asked him four years before his
death to write his biography.
[2] In 1980, at the French Biblioteque Nationale,
Jean Mistler, member of the French Academy, has found three books, printed in
Konigsberg, written by three members of the Luteran church, who were also students
of Kant: Borowski, Jachmann et Wasiansky. They were all about Kant’ life. Jean
Mistler translated and published them in 1985, under the title of Kant
intime (Paris: Grasset et Fasquelle, 1985).